Curbing Corporate
Power
Chapter 4 of The
Beauty Queens Guide to World Peace
By Dan Plesch
Politico's 2004
Contents Curbing corporate power
Corporate power The existing debate on corporate
power Unlimiting limited liability Limited
liability protects corruption The argument for
shareholdersÌ privilege Strategies for restoring
freedom
Curbing corporate power
People are ripped off, day in, day out, by the easy availability
of limited liability for off-the-shelf companies and the
protections provided for them, and with no real remedies.
Andrew Phillips, legal advisor on the BBC Jimmy Young
Show
According to the Atlantic Charter, international economic
cooperation after the Second World War was to include
the object of securing, for all, improved labour
standards, economic adjustment and social security.
This objective was a clear attempt to offer the removal
of economic grievances as a source of political conflict
and to rally support for a better postwar world. Popular
discontent over economic conditions and the widespread
popularity of both socialism and communism at that time
have been mostly forgotten today. The public provision
of health care, education, unemployment benefit and old-age,
pensions was improved by governments in Britain and the
rest of Europe immediately after the Second World War.
Today, fair working standards and social security are
under strong attack from neo-conservatives and neo-liberals
alike who see them as impediments to the free market and
the operation of corporations.
But the acceptance of world poverty, economic injustice
and the strengthening of a hugely wealthy elite is a recipe
for conflict and war. Battles for access to wealth have
been one of the greatest causes of international and civil
war since earliest times. On the other hand, shared prosperity
is a powerful force for peaceful conditions. William Cobbett,
the English eighteenth-century radical, remarked that
he defied anyone to agitate a man with a full stomach,
a double-edged remark conjuring up both the image of after-dinner
bloat and the desperation of those with empty stomachs.
This chapter reviews the great grievance felt around
the world over the uncontrollable power of corporations
and the continuation of poverty for the many. It recommends
that the power of big businesses can be balanced and controlled
by removing the special-interest protection that enables
the shareholders who own corporations to avoid legal responsibility
for the consequences of their actions. This protection
is called limited liability.
Corporate power
It is easy to believe that corporations run the world.
Their power is often greater than governmentsÌ;
sometimes we seem to exist only in order to consume their
products and boost their profits. WhatÌs good for
General Motors is good for America and the rest of the
world too. And if you donÌt like it ... it doesnt
matter because you are irrelevant, and in any case look
at all the wealth being created. Free markets work, despite
their problems, and there is simply no alternative - or
so we are told.
This attitude - triumphal from the supporters of big
business, wearily defeatist from those who try to restrain
them - pretty much describes the present corporate domination
of societies around the world. In the advanced democracies,
corporations are sweeping aside government controls and
socially owned organisations; in the rest of the world
the protections given to the wealthy through the limited-liability
laws provide a blank cheque for old and corrupt elites
in supposedly reformed and democratic societies.
Attempts to find voluntary means of controlling corporate
power have not had sufficient impact. There now needs
to be a debate about the need for legal reforms to make
shareholders and directors accountable for the actions
of the companies they own. A movement for this reform
should be the economic centrepiece of a global strategy
for stability and prosperity. Such reform is necessary
because existing attempts to obtain voluntary agreements
from corporations to behave well are not working. Many
people are unaware of the injustice created by limited
liability, and consequently it is necessary to make the
argument plainly and strongly. This does not mean that
I believe that there are millions of people out there
going to work every day saying to themselves, ÎGoody,
IÌm off to operate an unjust system.Ì The
dominance of limited liability has crept up on us over
the years; people are rarely if at all deliberately operating
a system that they are aware is unjust and violating the
human rights of their fellow citizens.The existing debate
on corporate power
Corporate power has grown considerably since the collapse
of communism and the widespread discrediting of state
socialist approaches to running society. Will Hutton has
argued with great clarity that the world as a whole has
to face the damaging consequences of the triumph of Anglo-American
business practice.1 Agreements in the World Trade Organisation
and the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development
(OECD) have extended and entrenched an agenda that favours
international corporations in the name of free trade and
free markets.
Huttons argument is echoed by many of those supporting
this approach. Two leading US academic economists, Henry
Hansmann and Reinier Kraakman, provide a typical example
of this analysis in their paper The End of History
for Corporate Law.2 They argue:
Despite the apparent divergence in institutions of governance,
share ownership, capital markets, and business culture
across developed economies, the basic law of the corporate
form has already achieved a high degree of uniformity,
and continued convergence is likely. A principal reason
for convergence is a widespread normative consensus that
corporate managers should act exclusively in the economic
interests of shareholders, including non-controlling shareholders.
This consensus on a shareholder-oriented model of the
corporation results in part from the failure of alternative
models of the corporation, including the manager-oriented
model that evolved in the US in the 1950Ìs and
60Ìs, the labor-oriented model that reached its
apogee in German co-determination, and the state-oriented
model that until recently was dominant in France and much
of Asia. Other reasons for the new consensus include the
competitive success of contemporary British and American
firms, the growing influence worldwide of the academic
disciplines of economics and finance, the diffusion of
share ownership in developed countries, and the emergence
of active shareholder representatives and interest groups
in major jurisdictions. Since the dominant corporate ideology
of shareholder primacy is unlikely to be undone, its success
represents the end of history for corporate law. The ideology
of shareholder primacy is likely to press all major jurisdictions
toward similar rules of
There is widespread public concern over the power of
corporations. The needs of business have come to define
politics today. The Anglo-American Third Way
and Britains New Labour have been attempts to fit
public demands for a fair and just society with the needs
of business. At a global level the strength and diversity
of resistance to a political agenda driven by the needs
of major corporations has been made evident by protests
at the world trade talks in Seattle and Cancun. Meanwhile,
Enron, WorldCom and similar scandals have produced a feeling
in the general public, and even amongst shareholders,
that they are being ripped off.
Attempts to make businesses behave better by campaigns
for what is called good corporate governance have had
little effect. Today, corporations usually follow the
legal advice that it is unlawful to pursue any other goal
than delivering profit to shareholders. Other social or
environmental objectives can be pursued, but they must
contribute to this primary goal. The enormous political
energy poured into corporate governance by so many people
can achieve very little because of this legal imperative.
A new strategy is needed to help corporations reinforce
rather than undermine the fabric of society. The reforms
I suggest would hold the major investors accountable in
law and give small investors more confidence that companies
were being run responsibly.
A close examination of the core of the common structure
of corporations reveals a fundamental injustice. Focusing
on the reform of this injustice should be the basis of
controlling corporations.
The key idea in the modern corporation is the concept
of limited liability. This concept provides the owners,
the shareholders, with complete power, but with no responsibility
for the consequences of their actions. Their liability
is limited to the sum of money they invest. This power
without responsibility is driving the whole structure
of global civilisation and yet it violates fundamental
principles of justice and human rights in a free society.
Limited liability creates inequality before the law by
allowing the most powerful to be above the law, when in
a free society all should be equal before the law.
Corporate law and practice.
The notion of organising the world around the needs of
shareholders has been questioned across the political
spectrum, from the World Social Forum at Porto Alegre
to the billionaire George Soros.3 Noam Chomsky,4 Naomi
Klein and George Monbiot are authors whose work provides
insights into the problems of corporate power and who
begin to suggest alternatives.
I do not wish to take time here to go over the familiar
arguments about the problems presented by uncontrolled
corporations beholden to their shareholders. But to summarise
the argument: corporations are accused of ignoring the
interests of those communities they hurt; of polluting
the air, land and water; and of forcing nations and communities
to give up nationalised and community-based businesses
and services. These problems are compounded by a tendency
for national and global markets to become dominated by
a handful of huge corporations. Their resources are often
larger than those of the countries in which they operate
and they are able to use structures of linked corporations
in many countries to avoid being held to account by the
governments of the countries in which they operate.
Think about cars, oil, accounting or pharmaceuticals,
for example. In each of these industries only a handful
of companies control the market. The problems caused by
these corporations have come to dominate the proceedings
of elite international gatherings such as the World Economic
Forum at Davos.
The opponents of corporate power suggest two main types
of strategy for opposing it: local initiatives and corporate
governance. Supporters of local initiatives, for example
Colin Hines in Localization: A Global Manifesto,5 propose
strengthening networks of local non-corporate economies
and cultures, such as cooperatives and schemes to promote
local produce. These networks include resistance to the
idea of third-world farmers being driven into producing
cash crops at the expense of existing, more integrated
and sustainable economies. An example in the developed
world is the network of Italian cities supporting local
produce and using local-authority regulations to keep
out global chains on the basis that they lack local content.
These initiatives appear to work well, but they are by
definition small scale, working at the edges of the economy.
They can provide a safe place to hide from the trampling
feet of the megacorps, but they are neither an effective
defence nor an effective means of control. They are, however,
a potential base from which such efforts at control can
be built.
In parallel with the growth of localism, there has also
been a movement to reach voluntary agreements with corporations
to persuade them to act with more consideration towards
the people and the environment that they affect. Often
termed corporate governance, this strategy
aims to persuade business to become more socially and
environmentally responsible. According to John Wolfensohn,
then President of the World Bank, Corporate governance
is about promoting corporate fairness, transparency and
accountability 6
The rebranding of British Petroleum as Beyond Petroleum
is an example of the effects of campaigns for corporate
responsibility. The company has, at least in its advertising,
engaged in social and environmental issues. Corporate
governance has led to a less confrontational and more
constructive relationship between pressure groups such
as Oxfam or Greenpeace and the business community, but
it has not led to much change.Christian Aids case
studies of corporate social
responsibility make a powerful case
The image of companies working hard to make the
world a better place is too often just that - a carefully
manufactured image, - says Behind the Mask:
The Real Face of Corporate Social Responsibility,
a new report from Christian Aid. Its target is the burgeoning
industry known as corporate social responsibility - or
CSR - which is now seen as a vital tool in promoting and
improving the public image of some of the worldÌs
largest companies and corporations.
But, as the case studies in this report - featuring Shell,
British American Tobacco and Coca-Cola - demonstrate,
the rhetoric can also mask corporate activity that makes
things worse for the communities in which they work.
Some of those shouting the loudest about their
corporate virtues are also among those inflicting continuing
damage on communities where they work - particularly poor
communities, says Andrew Pendleton, senior policy
officer at Christian Aid and author of the report. Legally
binding regulation is now needed to lessen the devastating
impact that companies can have in an ever-more globalised
world.
Christian Aid, January 2004Stock market scandals at the
end of the twentieth century revived a different type
of call for reform. This time it was not from those who
had bad experiences from the direct operations of corporations,
but from shareholders who lost money when the businesses
failed. Corporate misdeeds have produced periodic reforms
back into the nineteenth century. These reactions were
at times especially strong in the US. At the time of Presidents
Taft and Theodore Roosevelt in the late nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries, regulations against monopolies
and price-fixing were introduced and monopolies such as
that in the oil industry were broken up. The notorious
stock market crash of 1929 produced some useful regulation
of stock market activity and, under President Franklin
D. Roosevelt, a host of union-friendly legislation protecting
workers rights.
The latest scandals had two notable characteristics.
Accountants had themselves cooked the books on a massive
scale as their role morphed from being independent auditors
to becoming integrated into company operations as consultants.
Secondly, on the stock market, the corruption of independent
financial advisers into sales staff for particular companies
shares destroyed their hard-won reputation for impartiality.
The effort at reform after the excesses of the 1990s
has been weak and is already failing. The Financial Times
reported in August 2003 that William Donaldson, the new
chairman of the Securities and Exchange Commission, had
voiced worries that entrepreneurial zeal was being
stifled by regulations and new legal advice. And
Alan Greenspan, the guru chairing the US Central Bank,
said that such concerns might be one reason why
corporate investment was being held back.7
In Britain, the chairman of Unilever, Niall FitzGerald,
has elegantly described how demands for stronger corporate
governance have been deflected:
On corporate governance, the trade and industry department
should be congratulated for having resisted knee-jerk
legislation or regulation in the wake of the Enron and
WorldCom scandals. Initially it appeared too quick to
accept recommendations in the Higgs report on corporate
governance, but effective and extensive consultation has
led to an outcome acceptable to all parties. In future
such consultation will help head off a growing sense that
Britain is no longer as friendly a place for business.8
The final remark is interesting for its implied threat
that business might move elsewhere, not because Britain
may become unfriendly to business, but because it may
just not remain friendly enough. That this hostility to
better governance comes not from some dodgy speculator
but from a company which sells soap powder indicates that
the problem of improving corporate behaviour is deep-rooted.
As Andrew Phillips, Lord Phillips of Sudbury, explained,9
once a private company becomes a limited-liability company,
any thought that wider interests may be served is apt
to be set aside and even government studies on governance
pay little attention to broader issues:
As the chairman of a large family business [Cadbury]
put it when they finally went public, Îonce we became
a quoted company, we were answerable to our shareholders
in the same way as any other company and subject to the
same external disciplines. We are, therefore, not in a
position to make any special claims about the way in which
the business is run and the values which lie behind its
management, nor would it be right for us to do so.Ì
How sad, and how diminishing for our society.
The fact of the matter is that the only stakeholders of
the modern limited company recognised by law, beyond a
sidelong glance at employees, are the shareholders. Indeed,
the government report last month [January 2003] by a business
luminary, Derek Higgs, on the role of non-executive directors,
reinforces that narrow focus. In over one hundred pages
there is scarcely a nod in the direction of the wider
public interest, or of corporate citizenship. He repeatedly
asserts that the required attributes of such directors
are those of skills, knowledge and experience
without reference to their character, judgement or wisdom.
This reflects the reality, namely that most such businesses
operate within exceedingly introspective, two-dimensional
parameters.
One of Higgss key recommendation to improve corporate
governance is to widen the role of what are called non-executive
directors. These are people who sit on boards but are
not involved in the day-to-day running of the business.
Their purpose is mainly to protect the rights of investors
from managers and directors seeking to feather their own
nests.
One form of developing corporate responsibility is the
idea of stakeholding, which has been made popular by Will
Hutton. His approach focuses on the question of the distortions
caused by the requirement to maximise profits for shareholders.
He attempts to redress this distortion by suggesting a
change to company law that would require companies also
to take into account a broader range of people with an
interest in the companys activities. Such people
with an interest, or stake, in the company are termed
Ì. Key stakeholders, such as insurance companies,
pension funds and other large institutional investors,
could be made to control companies. Tony Blair had a brief
flirtation with stakeholding shortly before coming to
power in 1997. However, the negative reaction from business
led to his dropping the idea.
Stakeholding is an attractive idea because it offers
the prospect of involving a broader range of people in
a companys activities. But this also creates significant
problems of defining who does and does not have a stake
in the company, and precisely what companies would have
to do to meet these somewhat ill-defined demands. Hutton
recommends that stakeholding be introduced by revisions
to company law. This would be welcome, but as he recognises,
it has so far failed to gather enough support. More fundamentally,
although it adds some rights to people who are not shareholders,
the stakeholding concept does not emphasise restoring
natural responsibilities on shareholders for the consequences
of their actions.
A number of economists and business leaders have always
rejected the idea that business should have a conscience
and so far this view prevails. Milton Friedman10 consistently
argued that anything that reduces the priority of delivering
financial returns to shareholders is wrong. This view
predominates today, as is indicated by the definition
of corporate governance given by the OECD. The OECD is
a club of the worlds richest nations. Its view of
corporate governance is quite different from Wolfensohns.
According to the OECD,
Corporate governance is the system by which business corporations
are directed and controlled. The corporate governance
structure specifies the distribution of rights and responsibilities
among different participants in the corporation, such
as the board, managers, shareholders and other stakeholders,
and spells out the rules and procedures for making decisions
on corporate affairs. By doing this, it also provides
the structure through which the company objectives are
set, and the means of attaining those objectives and monitoring
performance.11
There is nothing here about fairness, transparency and
accountability. This definition is concerned with the
rights and responsibilities of corporate decision-making.
The application of this narrow definition of corporate
responsibility is intended to ensure that business plays
by the rules and minimises corruption. An example of this
approach is a speech to key Chinese business leaders by
BritainÌs top financial regulator, Howard Davies.12
His topic was Corporate Governance and the Development
of Global Capital Markets. That is to say, he was
discussing the ways in which corporate governance matters
to the development of global capitalism. His key point
is that corruption in business makes doing business more
expensive and so less attractive to investors coming from
outside a particular culture:
Another, harder piece of evidence comes from some American
research on the cost of capital. US academic researchers
have found that in countries where the policing of insider
trading is regarded as weak, or where the legal framework
is poor, the cost of capital for firms is typically some
3 percentage points higher than in countries where insider
dealing is policed effectively.
So good corporate governance, and effective regulation,
contribute both to the attractiveness of a country in
terms of inward investment and business development, and
also to the efficiency of its capital markets, and their
effectiveness in the service of the real economy. It is
always as well to remember these points when considering
what can sometimes be a rather dry topic. And it is important
to make these arguments robustly to those who argue that
efforts devoted to upgrading corporate governance are
costly and bureaucratic, and add little value to the economy.
In my view, investment in good corporate governance arrangements,
and good regulation of those arrangements, is among the
most effective and rewarding investments a developing
market can make, and there are figures to prove it.
These are important objectives as far as they go but
they ignore the broader question of the relationship of
the corporation to society.
The concept of corporate governance contains no financial
or legal power to correct business behaviour beyond improving
returns to shareholders. It is an ill-defined approach
that absorbs enormous energy from NGOs, academics, unions,
government departments and businesses. After more than
a decade of political activity, attempts to control businesses
through this approach have failed to produce results that
even keep up with the problems.
Another approach to controlling corporations has centred
on the idea of increasing the power of shareholders. In
large modern corporations, the directors and managers
of the business have come to assume a very large degree
of power. Shareholders often own too few shares, are too
ill-informed, or are simply too uninterested to get a
grip on company operations. The scandals of the 1990s
referred to earlier, produced new calls for accountability
to shareholders as a means of preventing financial mismanagement.
It is this type of concern that the Higgs report in Britain
and new regulations from the US Securities and Exchange
Commission were meant to address. But, unfortunately,
it is these very same constraints that the leading business
figures quoted earlier were so keen to cast aside. The
push for shareholder accountability is thus proving as
ineffective as the governance and stakeholding efforts
to control corporations.
Pressure groups have often used purchasing shares as
a means of putting corporate behaviour in the spotlight.
The idea is that as shareowners, protestors can gain access
to the annual general meetings of corporations and then
ask questions and make points during the meeting. A typical
example comes from Greenpeace in New Zealand, where it
was seeking to stop pollution:
Greenpeace campaigns dont always end up in inflatable
boats or with activists locked on to smokestacks. We took
the Auckland International Airport Ltd (AIAL) incineration
campaign straight to the boardroom challenging AIAL to
live up to its vision through a shareholder resolution
at their AGM. Greenpeace purchased the minimum number
of shares to allow it to take the resolution forward.
Greenpeace board chair Gordon Duncan and campaigner Sue
Connor presented the argument for a clean alternative
to a packed AGM in Auckland. Residents of Mangere community,
located downwind of the incinerator, also attended to
convey their concerns.
The resolution was not formally passed but there was
a lot of support for its spirit. AIAL can be left in no
doubt that this is an important issue for many individual
and corporate shareholders.
AIAL agreed to fulfil the demand of Manukau City Council,
the third largest shareholder, that the company urgently
investigate alternative ways of treating their waste.
However, they have yet to make any real change.
Greenpeace will continue to put pressure on AIAL to ensure
that the investigation is robust and that the true social
and environmental costs of incineration are taken in to
account. Any thorough investigation will show the only
viable option is to move to a cleaner alternative such
as steam sterilisation.
This type of activity can be used to forward the public
interest, but it is rare that these activist shareholders
have the money and numbers to win at the end of the day.
Nevertheless, the tactic serves to highlight the privileged
immunity that shareholders enjoy. Greenpeace had rights
to debate with the company because it became a part-owner
in it. Had Greenpeace members just been citizens standing
choking in the fumes, the company would have had no automatic
duty to engage with them.
Unlimiting limited liability
Most businesses are organised as companies with a legal
structure in which the shareholders hold limited liability.
This means that if the company fails or causes damage,
the shareholders only lose the sum of money they invested.
The company is designed to provide them with money, while
protecting them from the responsibility for their actions
or inactions in relation to it. A company can be prosecuted
or sued if it sells defective products, destroys the environment
or sells weapons to the enemy, but its shareholders are
immune. Shareholders have regulated protection, at a time
when other regulation is being swept away in their favour.
Company directors also escape personal liability, seemingly
because they are agents of shareholders, who are not liable.
Nowadays, directors seem to exist in a privileged twilight
zone beyond the reach of shareholders and public alike.
Shareholders' power without responsibility is central
to the problem of corporate globalisation. Shareholders
are the greatest beneficiaries of government regulation,
yet demand that only they enjoy the protection of such
regulation. As corporate power has grown, shareholders
together have exercised vast powers over the world economy
without having to take responsibility for the consequences
of their actions. Some of the worst examples of abuse
in fact come from undemocratic societies, or societies
with elites that have recently moved from communism to
democracy. All too often these cliques have neatly grabbed
a nationÌs assets during privatisation and find
that the protected existence of a United States-style
economic aristocracy provides them with an even more special
status than they enjoyed so recently as members of the
Communist Party elites.
To restore the balance in society, shareholders
limited liability must be deregulated so that they no
longer hold a special status. The very phrase free
marketÌ is a nonsense because the special interests
of shareholders are protected from free-market forces.
The economist Adam Smith was one of the first to identify
the problems of limited liability companies, or joint-stock
companies, as they were originally called (and are so
still in some parts of the world, such as Russia). Joint-stock
companies had first been developed by the Dutch and were
quickly taken up in London when the Dutchman William of
Orange became King William III of England in 1689. The
first stock market speculations and crashes came soon
afterwards, the crashes following on from scams involving
Dutch tulips and the famous South Sea Bubble.
This was not, as I fondly imagined as a child, some gigantic
soap bubble Ò perhaps blown by a whale Ò
but an investment con selling the idea of luxury imports
from newly discovered territories in the oceans of the
Southern hemisphere.
It was against this background that Smith considered
limited-liability companies in The Wealth of Nations,
his great book on free-market economics, published in
1776. In it he generally opposes the development of limited-liability
companies, though he saw a limited value for them in the
construction of some public works.13
Adam Smith denounces limited liability in The Wealth
of Nations (emphasis added)
Joint stock companies, established either by royal
charter or by act of parliament, differ in several respects,
not only from regulated companies, but from private copartneries.
First, in a private copartnery, no partner, without the
consent of the company, can transfer his share to another
person, or introduce a new member into the company. Each
member, however, may, upon proper warning, withdraw from
the copartnery, and demand payment from them of his share
of the common stock. In a joint stock company, on the
contrary, no member can demand payment of his share from
the company; but each person can, without their consent,
transfer his share to another person, and thereby introduce
a new member. The value of a share in a joint stock is
always the price which it will bring in the market; and
this may be either greater or less, in any proportion,
than the sum which its owner stands credited for in the
stock of the company.
Secondly, in a private copartnery, each partner is bound
for the debts contracted by the company to the whole extent
of his fortune. In a joint stock company, on the contrary,
each partner is bound only to the extent of his share.
The Trade of a joint stock company is always managed
by a court of directors. The court, indeed, is frequently
subject, in many respects, to the control of a general
court of proprietors. But the greater part of those proprietors
seldom pretend to understand anything of the business
of the company; and when the spirit of faction happens
not to prevail among them, give themselves no trouble
about it, but receive contentedly such half yearly or
yearly dividend, as the directors think proper to make
to them. This total exemption from trouble and from risk,
beyond a limited sum, encourages many people to become
adventurers in joint stock companies, who would, upon
no account, hazard their fortunes in any private copartnery
... The directors of such companies, however, being the
managers rather of other peoples money than their
own, it cannot well be expected that they should watch
over it with the same anxious vigilance with which the
partners in a private copartnery frequently watch over
their own. Like the stewards of a rich man, they are apt
to consider attention to small matters as not for their
masters honour, and very easily give themselves
dispensation from having it. Negligence and profusion,
therefore, must always prevail, more or less, in the management
of the affairs of such a company.
* * *
To establish a joint stock company, however, for any
undertaking, merely because such a company might be capable
of managing it successfully; or to exempt a particular
set of dealers from some of the general laws which take
place with regard to all their neighbours, merely because
they might be capable of thriving if they had such an
exemption, would certainly not be reasonable. To render
such an establishment perfectly reasonable ... it ought
to appear with the clearest evidence that the undertaking
is of greater and more general utility than the greater
part of common trades. ... The joint stock companies,
which are established for the public-spirited purpose
of promoting some particular manufacture, over and above
managing their own affairs ill, to the diminution of the
general stock of the society, can in other respects scarce
ever fail to do more harm than good. Notwithstanding the
most upright intentions, the unavoidable partiality of
their directors to particular branches of the manufacture,
of which the undertakers mislead and impose upon them,
is a real discouragement to the rest, and necessarily
breaks, more or less, that natural proportion which would
otherwise establish itself between judicious industry
and profit, and which, to the general industry of the
country, is of all encouragements the greatest and the
most effectual.
So, the man held up as the ancestral guru of the business
world disapproved of the legal structure of most modern
businesses. He also provided an analysis that accurately
describes the concerns many feel about company mismanagement
today. Company directors act as the stewards
of the rich absentee landlords - the shareholders. However,
in the contemporary world the annual general meeting has
minimal power. Perhaps it needs to be reinvigorated as
the Îgeneral court of proprietorsÌ mentioned
by Smith.
Smiths condemnation of limited liability is omitted
from the way his views are handed down by free-market
advocates. BritainÌs Adam Smith Institute is a
bastion of corporate rights. Fans of globalisation such
as Philippe Legrain find it useful to cite SmithÌs
wisdom in support of their arguments, but omit his critique
of the structure of modern capitalism. Even Arnold Schwarzenegger
cited The Wealth of Nations as one of the most important
books in his life, though he is scarcely an advocate of
repealing limited liability.
Smiths concerns over limited liability are discussed
by John Micklethwait and Adrian Wooldridge in their recent
hymn to corporations, The Company: A Short History of
a Revolutionary Idea.14 They state that Smith had two
objections to limited liability: that such companies were
inefficient and tended in his day to be monopolies. Whatever
the merits of these objections, Micklethwait and Wooldridge
fail to consider at all SmithÌs main objection,
namely that society should not exempt
some people from general laws simply because they may
thrive as a result.
It may seem a startling idea to reform or remove limited
liability. We look back at past ages and think, how could
people have put up with an obvious injustice like feudal
serfdom or the slave trade? Perhaps when you are born
and brought up in such a system it seems natural and it
would be dangerous to tamper with it. Squire knows
best, mutters the peasant in many a period drama.
A similar fear exists around business: It has always
been like this and the economy will collapse if we challenge
the basis of corporate organisation.
Blindness to the issue of shareholder responsibility
is illustrated in the recent Progressive Manifesto edited
by Anthony Giddens, which offers new ideas for the centre-left.
He argues that citizens need to take much greater responsibility,
rather than relying so much on state provisions, but the
key powerful class of shareholders is not even mentioned.
The focus is on the mostly economically weak recipients
of government money: they are the ones who have to change
their ways. Nevertheless, there are some outright critics
of limited liability, such as the Australian academic
John Quiggen, who points out that many economists criticised
the proposals for limited-liability laws in the nineteenth
century. In the US, David Korten has written powerfully
againstthe problem of limited liability.15
Equality before the law is often cited as one of the
fundamental rights of a free society. It is enshrined
in Article 7 of the 1948 United Nations Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, which states: All are equal before
the law and are entitled without any discrimination to
equal protection of the law. All are entitled to equal
protection against any discrimination in violation of
this Declaration and against any incitement to such discrimination.
But, as Smith pointed out so succinctly two hundred years
ago, to exempt a particular set of dealers from
some of the general laws which take place with regard
to all their neighbours, merely because they might be
capable of thriving if they had such an exemption, would
certainly not be reasonable.
Does this exemption amount to inequality? Well, that
is what exemption means. Some people may argue that the
limited-liability laws have been created democratically.
This is true but also irrelevant since they can also be
repealed democratically. The debate should be about changing
the law which provides for this inequality, and it is
clear that those who cling to the way things are believe
that this inequality is a good thing, helping make society
as a whole better off, and that to threaten this inequality
is merely destructive nihilism.
It is also true that shareholding was entrenched in the
Western democracies long before the Universal Declaration
on Human Rights. So, again I can hear an argument coming:
Since shareholding existed before modern human-rights
law, then surely it cannot be affected by it. This
argument is similar to an infamous argument over the US
Constitution. It is based on the assumption made in the
Declaration of Independence: We hold these truths
to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that
they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable
Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit
of Happiness. However, when it was written, few
of the men who approved it would admit that black people
were people at all. They were merely property. The point
of relevance to the limited-liability debate is that it
is possible to re-examine how definitions are applied
as circumstances change.
It is especially helpful to reopening the debate over
limited liability that there is a history of clear criticism
from leading public figures all the way back to the time
when limited liability was first introduced. Today the
social damage created by limited-liability companies has
become the major focus of political concern about the
global economy and is overdue for reform.
In theory such reform should be a concern of American
conservative and libertarian lawyers such as the Federalist
Society, who aim to roll back laws that they construe
as going beyond the statements of the Founding Fathers.
Limited liability is the most damaging and glaring example
of going beyond the intent of the Founding Fathers by
creating a whole class of people exempt from the law.
To summarise, limited liability can be seen as removing
the human right of the vast majority of people on the
planet to equality before the law, the core value of a
free society.
Limited liability protects corruption
When I started considering the reform of company law
I stumbled over a legal idea that seems to come from Lord
of the Rings or Buffy the Vampire Slayer Ò Îpiercing
the corporate veilÌ.
In the imposing terminology of the legal profession,
there is a ÎveilÌ that protects shareholders
from liability. Now, I am sure that legal historians will
be able to find all sorts of explanations for the evolution
of this term. The veil is worn by women to hide their
sexuality or grief, customary in Muslim societies and
made erotic in the dance of the seven veils; this is the
legal concept upon which corporate globalisation rests,
a veil through which shareholders can see but not be seen,
a one-way mirror, a one-way street of power where they
can act but not be acted upon. I would have thought that
both Freudian psychoanalysis and feminist theory would
have generated a few dozen PhD theses on the imagery invoked
by this idea, but sadly I have not found any.
The concept of "piercing the veilÌ describes
some barely known circumstances in which under certain
states" laws shareholders can be held liable for
their actions. According to one British specialist discussing
a case relating to claims for asbestos-related injuries
that were thwarted by layers of Russian-doll-like limited-liabilitycompanies
with one hiding inside another:
Any modern consideration of lifting the corporate veil
must almost certainly begin with the decision of the Court
of Appeal in Adams v Cape Industries [1991] 1 All ER 929.
The case saw the most detailed judicial review of this
aspect of company law ever undertaken in the UK. Justice
Scott, and then the Court of Appeal, refused to allow
the veil to be lifted on an English parent company whose
American subsidiary had been successfully sued by American
litigants but which had insufficient assets to satisfy
judgement. Lord Justice Slade said: "Our law, for
better or worse, recognises the creation of subsidiary
companies, which though in one sense the creatures of
their parent companies, will nevertheless under the general
law fall to be treated as separate legal entities with
all the rights and liabilities which would normally attach
to separate legal entities." The law will not permit
the lifting of the corporate veil just because the interests
of justice would be better served by doing so.16
This specialist went on to say that the veil of incorporation
may be lifted where a company is a sham and no third party
has an involvement with it. It may also be lifted where
the company is a party to a fraud. It will not be lifted
just because justice demands it. A director can escape
personal liability to a third party in negligence by acting
through his company and ensuring that he is perceived
as accepting no personal liability for what he is doing.
He cannot escape personal liability where he acts fraudulently
on behalf of his company. A similar legal protection exists
in the US.17
Even in a key organ of corporate globalisation, the OECD,
there is a recognition that this type of activity, especially
when hidden behind the seven veils of subsidiary companies,
does represent an obstacle to shareholders turning an
honest profit. The 2001 OECD study ÎBehind the Corporate
Veil: Using Corporate Entities for Illicit PurposesÌ
concludes:
Corporate entities Ò corporations, trusts, foundations
and partnerships Ò are often misused for money
laundering, bribery and corruption, shielding assets from
creditors, tax evasion, self-dealing, market fraud and
other illicit activities. The veil of secrecy they provide
in some jurisdictions may also facilitate the flow of
funds to terrorist organisations.
Behind the Corporate Veil concludes that
the types of corporate entities that are most frequently
misused are those that provide the greatest degree of
anonymity to their beneficial owners. In response, the
OECD calls on governments and other relevant authorities
to ensure they are able to obtain information on the beneficial
ownership and control of corporate entities and, where
appropriate, to share this information with law enforcement
authorities domestically and internationally. Specifically,
the OECD recommends that governments should consider taking
action to:
Require up front disclosure of beneficial ownership
and control information to the authorities upon the formation
of the corporate vehicle;
Oblige intermediaries involved in the formation
and management of corporate vehicles (such as company
formation agents, trust companies, lawyers, trustees,
and other professionals) to maintain such information;
Develop the appropriate law enforcement infrastructure
to enable them to launch investigations into beneficial
ownership and control when illicit activity is suspected.
As should now be clear, it is now the company that gets
sued; even though the company is not actually a person,
just an idea, the law says that a company is treated as
a person. A limited-liability company can simply be the
expendable fall guy that can be declared bankrupt or shut
down while the shareholders are long gone. Companies have
additional structures to protect themselves even further.
This is through the creation of subsidiary companies.
In this case the subsidiary may be sued but its parent
company cannot because it is the shareholder. In this
way a further incentive to irresponsible behaviour has
been created.
The argument for shareholders
privilege
John Micklethwait and Adrian Wooldridge uphold a tradition
of enthusiastic supporters of limited liability. They
assert that the most important organisation in the
world is the company: the basis of the prosperity of the
West and the best hope of the rest of the world.
This is the main idea used to defend the special-interest
protection enjoyed by shareholders. It is at least odd
to hear the argument that limited liability provides a
unique public benefit from those who argue at the same
time that there must be no public duty at all placed upon
shareholders and companies. They seem to be saying, Look,
we are making the whole world work, dont mess it
up. In addition, there is the argument that there
is no real privilege because anyone can buy shares or,
as Marie Antoinette might have said, anyone can
buy cake.
Limited liability is credited with creating the vast
increase in wealth since the Industrial Revolution. Any
attempt to tamper with it will meet great resistance.
Even calls for a minimum wage and for social security
have been thought to have the potential to cause lasting
damage to business. The first time I raised the issue
of deregulating shareholder immunity, I came across the
vehement objection of a group of venture capitalists.
They argued that even raising the prospect of suing shareholders
would damage investor confidence and was therefore a dangerous
idea. It is certainly true that a market in stocks and
shares has been an effective means of raising capital
for businesses for more than two hundred years. Some people
believe that raising money in this way is essential to
the organisation of the economy.
The Industrial Revolution was well under way before the
limited liability became the norm.18 The joint-stock company
with tradable shares was not made generally available
for business activities in England until 1844, and limited
liability was not added to the form until 1855. While
some American states developed the form for general use
a few years earlier, all general business corporation
statutes appear to date from well after 1800. By around
1900, however, every major commercial jurisdiction appears
to have provided for at least one joint-stock company.
As the BBCs History Timeline explains, this allowed
companies to limit the liability of their individual investors
to the value of their shares. Prior to this, investors
in a company stood to lose all their wealth if economic
circumstances forced the company they had invested in
out of business. The curtailing of risk as a result of
the act is credited with being the basis for the increased
investment in trade and industry, although most of the
evidence for this is apocryphal.19
Until the 1930s in the US there were two major exceptions
to limited liability. California not only had no limited-liability
law, but it insisted that companies based in other parts
of the US did not have limited liability in California.
The US banking system did not operate under limited liability
either.
Different approaches to liability were used in these
instances. In California there was a system called pro-rata
liability.20 Pro-rata liability means that in addition
to risking their investment, shareholders are responsible
for the debts of the company in proportion to the amount
of the company they own. Own one per cent of the shares
and be responsible for one per cent of the debt. In the
US banking sector it was common until the 1930s for shareholders
to be responsible for the debts of the company to the
extent of two or three times the face value of the shares
that they owned. The face value is the value of the shares
when they were sold to the public. For example, a company
might offer 1,000,000 £1 shares for sale on the
stock market, they might then be traded at a value of
10p or £10, but the liability would be based on
the issued share price of £1.
There have been a few studies that attempt to provide
evidence that unlimited liability can work as well as
or better than limited.21 Lewis Evans and Neil Quigley
studied the legal structure of shareholding in the banking
industry of nineteenth-century Scotland. At this time
some banks used the system of limited liability that we
know so well today, while others used a system of unlimited
liability. This was at a time when Scottish capital was
playing a crucial role in the financial development of
the British Empire. They found that in some special circumstances,
unlimited liability might even be more effective. A study
by Mark Weinstein22 of the introduction of limited liability
in California found that it had no discernible effect
on the stock market price of companies shares, although
at that time Californians had not developed the art of
suing corporations, still less their shareholders. This
form of company law, which I will call traditional
Californian capitalism, has much to offer the twenty-first
century.
In the modern age, perhaps the most famous and largest
example of unlimited, rather than limited, liability is
the practice in the London insurance market run by Lloyds.
Lloyds of London has for many years been the major
insurer of businesses in the world. Under this system
people known as ÎnamesÌ agree to put their
entire wealth at risk to guarantee the insurance market.
As a result of their willingness to accept an unlimited
risk they receive high returns on their investments. For
many years, the insurance industry was regarded as a source
of great wealth for those already wealthy. Regardless
of its recent problems where some insurers have gone bankrupt,
LloydÌs of London provides an example of a key
part of the structure of international business that is
not run on the basis of limited liability. The existence
of such a key, world-leading industry, not reliant on
a limited-liability structure, is of great importance.
It provides a substantial example to counter those who
argue that limited liability is the only way global markets
can operate.
Professions such as law, accountancy and architecture
have all operated as successful businesses for many years
without the protection of limited liability. However,
starting in the US, a new concept of limited liability
has been introduced to allow these professionals to escape
liability for their actions. When new laws were proposed
in Britain to extend limited liability to the professions,
Phillips made a vain attempt to at least force companies
to advertise any previous names they had used to conduct
business. In debate, the government minister makes a crack
at Phillipss own profession of law:23
Lord McIntosh of Haringey: But was it not Adam
Smith who also said that all professions were a conspiracy
against the laity?
Lord Phillips of Sudbury: That is precisely why
I have opposed this Bill stock, root and branch. I am
a great admirer of my own profession. But I am afraid
that this measure is apt to be a conspiracy against the
public interest from start to finish. However, I am more
concerned with the small traders who will take advantage
of the special privileges of this Bill. Let us make no
bones about it; this will provide your two-man cowboy
building outfit with a uniquely flexible and light framed
means of screwing the public, to put it in Anglo-Saxon
terms ... One of my jobs is that of legal adviser on the
Jimmy Young Show. Over 25 years I have heard of hundreds
of thousands of cases of abuse in relation to small, local
companies that get nowhere near the attention of the DTI
and get nowhere near being addressed by the various provisions
to which the Minister refers. It depresses me that in
this House we are so far out of touch with public opinion,
if I may put it this way, at the bottom end of the social
spectrum. People are ripped off, day in, day out, by the
easy availability of limited liability for off-the-shelf
companies and the protections provided for them, and with
no real remedies.
Supporters of the expansion of limited liability as the
dominant form of social organisation downplay other economic
models, including European social democracy and various
forms of Japanese and south-east Asian economies that
have all produced significant and sustained economic growth
in the contemporary world. In much of the world and indeed
in much of US history, shareholder privilege was balanced
by other laws and powers in society. At present these
balanced and socialised forms of business are under attack.
This may be because they are less effective, or simply
because they provide fewer benefits to those with power.
Today corporations and their political allies are seeking
to sweep all of these protections away. Rather than resist
this by defending the more socially integrated forms of
business, it will be more effective to attack the injustice
fundamental to unfettered shareholder power.
The idea that the economy can only function when property-owners
are protected from having any responsibility for their
actions is not historically accurate. It is easy to forget
that an international economy had existed and prospered
for thousands of years before the invention of limited
liability. Business and trade are ancient practices that
have been helped and hindered by the social practices
of the times. In England for example, Cornish tin-miners
were trading successfully as far away as the Mediterranean
even before the Roman Empire. Trade and business are as
old as civilisation.One of the reasons most often given
on behalf of business and shareholders for the continuation
of limited liability is that anyone can freely choose
to go into business or invest through buying shares. Millions
of people own shares through their pension schemes or
through investment companies that manage the money of
many small investors. There is no doubt that this has
benefited many millions of people, myself included; however,
even in the US only one-half of all households participate
in the stock market through pension plans, and of these
households very few have more than a tiny proportion of
the shares of any one company. It will be simple to if
necessary, make a cut-off point for liability for small
shareholders Ò just so long as that does not provide
a loophole for large institutional investors. In any case,
the major corporations, institutions and the super-rich
are the groups that own significant parts of major companies.
As has been demonstrated in the studies by Professor Edward
N. Wolff of New York University in 1989,24 ten per cent
of US families owned eighty-nine per cent of stocks and
bonds traded on the stock exchange. Since then these concentrations
have increased. Similar concentrations of wealth protected
by limited-liability laws now exist around the world.
US families are classified into wealth class by Wolff
on the basis of their net worth. In the top one per cent
of the wealth distribution (the Super Rich)
are families with a net worth of $2.35 million or more
in 1989; in the next nine per cent (the Rich)
are families with a net worth greater than or equal to
$346,400 but less than $2.35 million; in the bottom ninety
per cent (Everybody Else) are families with
a net worth less than $346,400:
Stocks Bonds
Super Rich 46.2% 54.2%
Rich 43.1% 34.3%
Everybody Else 10.7% 11.5%
Supporters of mass shareholding often make exaggerated
claims that a few years down the road result in great
disappointment. In the 1980s Margaret Thatchers
government had TV advertising campaigns trying to persuade
members of the public to buy shares in the newly privatised
utilities. A few years later large corporations were buying
out these small shareholders Ò few had ever bought
more shares and the cost of providing them with information
was very uneconomic for the privatised companies. During
the stock market boom of the 1990s conservative politicians
in the US and Britain began to campaign to privatise social-security
holdings. This would have meant that this money was no
longer held by the government bank but could be invested
in companies. This idea was becoming fashionable until
there was a sudden dramatic fall in the stock market,
after which little more was heard of the idea.
Strategies for restoring freedom
As I have discussed, the idea of freeing the market from
special-interest protections and distortions should have
special appeal in the US. Conservative and libertarian
lawyers and activists are keen to remove regulations of
all kinds. In their key network the Federalist Society
they argue for some particular views of what they see
as the original US Constitution and oppose laws that seek
to develop and change policy with time. From this perspective,
limited liability is a classic example of a distortion
of the clear constitutional principle of equality before
the law.
For Americans, restoring equal rights may be an especially
important argument for creating a more equal society.
This is because it destroys the myth that the rich are
rich by dint of hard work or inheritance and that any
tax to help the less well off is simply theft to assist
the lazy. Exposing limited liability for what it is, explodes
this delusion once and for all.
From the left, Professor Harry Glasbeek has argued: There
is an entirely plausible argument to be made that criminal
law should hold major shareholders responsible for the
many evils done by the corporation on their behalf. And
many social and environmental campaigners are now focusing
their attentions on the laws that allow shareholders and
investors the protection of their invisible friend
- the legal fiction that is the corporation.25
Sue the shareholders may look good on a protest
banner. But to be effective, a campaign to restore equal
freedoms to the economic market needs to have some practical
intermediate stages. In general terms a clear understanding
of the special status enjoyed by shareholders should make
it easier to argue for balancing rights for community
groups, elected governments and trade unions. More specifically,
there need to be some adjustments to the laws that govern
corporations. Fortunately, there are useful historical
examples. Two mentioned earlier should be considered.
These are the ideas of having a liability two or three
times the price of the share and of pro-rata liability.
The insurance system could be employed to help manage
the risk. Apart from shareholders, almost every person
in the industrialised world ends up needing insurance.
Our car insurance protects us if we damage someone else
or another car; every business needs public-liability
insurance. Rent a civic centre to throw a party and you
will find that, before you can, you will have to buy a
public-liability insurance policy. This is because if
someone is blinded by a party popper you could get sued.
Even your house insurance is likely to provide cover in
case a roof tile lands on someones head.
The contrast between what does and does not need to be
insured is easy to illustrate. Oxford University has a
service for its academics looking to spin off limited-liability
companies. It provides a fairly typical list of the types
of insurance that will be needed: The spin-out will
need to obtain a number of insurance policies including:
directors, and officers, insurance; building and contents
insurance; employers liability insurance; public
liability insurance and product liability insurance.
No sign of shareholder insurance.
The creation of insurance for shareholders could be a
relatively simple way of re-establishing equality before
the law and placing shareholders as normal citizens with
responsibility for their actions equivalent to everyone
else in society.
Some people may argue that the insurance industry is
already too powerful and has introduced too much nannying
in society. If the insurance industry is itself behaving
badly this is perhaps because it too has to provide maximum
returns to shareholders, something a reform of limited
liability would help solve. Insurance is an industry quite
well suited to nationalisation or to non-profit status.
Social insurance for health and old age are two of the
best-known examples of the nation taking responsibility
for insurance provision. Another less well-known example
is where the nation underwrites mass damage from a terrorist
attack, an innovation made in the UK after the Provisional
IRA attacks on the City of London in the mid-1990s.
Restoring equality before the law will help many social,
economic and environmental campaigns. The removal or reduction
of limited liability would ensure that power does not
come without responsibility. This would do much to redress
the imbalance between the powerful and the powerless.
The accelerating power of the business interest would
be likely to come to an abrupt halt if it were faced with
such a direct challenge to its privilege. Such a challenge
would affect the organisation of thousands of companies
all over the world. The mere threat of having their privilege
exposed may encourage better behaviour.
The argument that the regulations protecting shareholders
should be removed can be used as a direct reply to corporate
demands for deregulation of other aspects of the market.
Opponents of increasing corporate power can argue that
the deregulation agenda pursued by corporations had better
begin with the regulation that prevents citizens from
suing shareholders. This argument is a much more effective
lever than socialist demands for the abolition of capitalism
or the idea that companies should start behaving like
charities.
The removal or reduction of limited liability is consistent
with the universal values that power should be matched
with responsibility and that we all should be equal before
the law.
Within the US, the restoration of the right to sue is
a core American value that can be expressed in simple
language. In the developing world and in the new European
democracies, making shareholders liable can be a means
of bringing within the law the rampant corruption that
is aided and abetted by the immunity of limited liability.
Campaigning to be able to sue shareholders in the same
way as anyone else is a clear political demand that can
reinforce and complement existing efforts to limit the
damage caused by corporations. In recent years, attempts
by the public and pressure groups to tackle corporate
power have had several public campaigns. These include
debt, fair trade, privatisation and climate change. Each
of these has produced important and imaginative proposals,
gained considerable public support, but in the end made
insufficient progress.
When corporations destroy the environment, as for example
in the case of the tanker Exxon Valdez, which was wrecked
on the Alaskan coast, releasing vast quantities of oil
that devastated marine life in the region, massive lawsuits
can sometimes be brought against the company. All too
often, the corporation is found to have been driven by
the need to provide maximum returns to shareholders. But
these shareholders are immune from any normal duty of
care in carrying out their actions. Were it possible to
sue the shareholders, one can be sure that they or their
insurers would make much stronger demands upon the company
to be certain that it was not cutting corners to maximise
profit. Quite rightly, the environmental movement is concerned
to introduce stronger legislation requiring corporations
to act in an environmentally friendly manner. However,
if environmentalists include the proposal that shareholders
should no longer be above the law, then they are likely
to find that corporations might well begin to make concessions
to pre-empt demands on shareholders. In similar fashion,
corporate demands to remove regulations protecting the
environment should be met with a counterbalancing proposal
to make their stockholders environmentally responsible
in law.
Another area where removing special-interest protection
can help existing campaigns is in the area of deregulation
of public services. The demands for compulsory privatisation
of public services and nationalised industries have been
gaining ground continuously around the world since their
inception in the early days of Margaret Thatchers
government in the 1980s. The debate in Britain has seen
service after service put into private hands for the benefit
of shareholders. Most recently, the issue that has come
to the forefront of public attention is the use of private
medical concerns to supplement the NHS.
The issue of shareholder liability, or lack of it, is
especially interesting in the case of medical issues,
not least because most of us are now familiar with the
idea of suing incompetent doctors, administrators and
hospitals. But consider the difference. Let us suppose
that the same serious problem occurs in both an NHS and
a private hospital. In the NHS any compensation claim
will have to be met by the hospital and, if it runs out
of money, by the government in London. A private hospital
is in a very different situation. If it runs out of money
its directors can declare it bankrupt and simply walk
away from it. In the meantime, the shareholders could
have sold up, taking their earlier profits with them.
Even if their profits were made at the time that the medical
negligence occurred, no one can touch them.
These imaginary examples are designed to show how much
more powerful a campaign can be if it is reinforced with
the issue of making shareholders equal before the law.
The power of the argument can become mutually reinforced
if it is taken up simultaneously on a wide range of issues
and in a wide range of countries. The issue of making
shareholders behave like normal people has the potential
to focus the efforts of a lot of different campaigns.
Paul Kingsnorth has shown the diversity and also lack
of focus of the anti-globalisation movement in One No,
Many Yeses.26 I hope that reform of limited liability
can serve as a unifying interest.
Reforming limited liability should improve the overall
quality of business activity by providing a legal basis
on which to build the social responsibility that so many
people are working for from inside and outside corporations.
The proportional liability used in conservative Californian
capitalism can provide the basis of reform and should
be able to attract support from across the political spectrum,
including those who believe that governments should not
provide any protection to interest groups. These reforms
have the potential to help develop fairer societies less
open to exploitation by extremism.
This key economic reform will be most effective if it
is accompanied by improvements to the way we organise
democracy. Money and political power are the vital elements
of the way society is organised and reforms in each area
should support each other.
2004
Dan Plesch
Research Associate
Centre for International Studies and Diplomacy
SOAS, University of London
0771 2833909
www.danplesch.net
|